Research by Michael Behrent for
KÖNIGSBEGR IS DEAD by Max & Gilbert
I.
COSMOPOLIS
I.
Kant's Königsberg
A. German
Towns in the 18th Century
In the area roughly known in the 18th
century as "Germany" - a vague term corresponding to no clear
"nation" in the modern sense of the word, even if the Holy Roman
Empire came closest to giving it some political form - there existed some 2000
cities, of which Königsberg was one. For the most part, these towns were
distinguished less by the features we have come to associate with modern cities
- a mobile, often transient population, an openness in spirit, a predisposition
to innovation - than they were by their stability and a rootedness in tradition.
One can even speak of a "self-conscious insularity" in German towns
of these periods: in the midst of what remained an overwhelmingly rural and
agricultural society, cities walled themselves up from the surrounding
countryside, restricted citizenship (Buergertum)
and staunchly defended the privileges granted to them by royal authorities.[1]
Though organically linked to a surrounding hinterland, which supplied the towns
with natural resources and to which they provided markets for their goods, as
well as to international trade routes, these towns were for the most part
socially stable and culturally conservative.
Yet even if these towns were insular by
contemporary standards, forces were at play in the 18th century that
contributed to integrating them into wider and more transformative relations
than they belonged to when they were founded in the Middle Ages. Towns located
on the Baltic shore from the Danish sound to Memel, historically associated
with the Hanseatic League [dates?], engaged in an intricate network of trade in
such goods as grain, salt, fish, lumber, flax and hemp. Being situated along
these relatively far-flung routes meant that the social texture of these towns
was less tightly woven then elsewhere: the presence of bankers, merchants and shippers
made available capital and connections unknown to more locally based business;
there were greater distinctions between social groups; a larger share of
laborers worked outside the framework of guilds. Yet whereas markets of this
type had already existed for several centuries, a newer force of transformation
was the state. Increasingly, large, bureaucratized states standardized and
centralized the patchwork of urban privileges that had proliferated since the
Middle Ages: for instance, the promulgation of the new Prussian legal code, the
Allgemeines Landrecht, in 1794,
placed the regulation of urban guilds under the authority of the Prussian
state.
B. Königsberg
in the 18th Century
Königsberg in the 18th century
was a characteristic German town situated on the
Physically, it was a town with a roughly
14 kilometer circumference situated on the
Economically, Königsberg's status as a
port town brought it into contact with other towns along the Baltic and in
Königsberg's population during this period
was somewhere between 40,000 and 50,000 inhabitants (not including the garrison
population). Though a "German" town, it was culturally,
linguistically and socially diverse. It continued to be marked by its Slavic
past (until 1660, Königsberg had been formally under Polish suzerainty). Trade
representatives and seaman from
In
addition to merchants, Königsberg's had other institutions that served as
magnets to attract people from elsewhere. It was, in the first place, the provincial
capital of
II.
Königsberg's Kant
A. Early
Life
Immanuel Kant was born in Königsberg on
April 22 - "Immanuel Day", according to the Prussian calendar - in a
house on Sadler [German?] Street, near the Grüne Brücke. He was thus born in a
neighborhood that, especially in the summer, would have been a vibrant trading
center, and a crossroads at which Germans, Jews, Dutch, English and Poles would
regularly cross paths.
Kant's
origins were modest. His father, John George Cant, had been born in
Though Kant grew up amidst the crowded
bustle of the city, he grew familiar with the more peaceful environs. In his
old age, he would recall how his mother would take him for walks outside the
city's fortified walls: "Often she took me outside of the city, directed
my attention to the works of God, spoke with pious rapture of His omnipotence,
wisdom and goodness, and impressed on my heart a deep reverence for the Creator
of all things."[2]
It was to his family's faith that Kant
owed his opportunity to consider a fate other than the modest one to which his
family origins might have destined him. The family pastor, Dr. Schulz,
recognizing the young Kant's talents, had him enrolled in the Collegium
Fridericianum, the Pietistic school which Schulz himself directed. From here,
Kant went on to attend his town's university, the Albertina, where he enrolled
himself in 1740, at the age of 16 (it is not known in which faculty he was initially
registered).
At the time that Kant entered university,
the major movements which were shaping intellectual life in the age were
Pietism and the spirit of Aufklärung - "Enlightenment",
or Lumières.
B. Intellectual
Influences: Pietism and Aufklärung.
Pietism was a major religious movement within the
Aufklärung is the name used to describe newfound
self-confidence of intellectuals and the educated classes in 18th
century
The Aufklärung spirit was not only present
in philosophical and scientific thought. It also deeply marked politics,
especially in Prussia: King Frederick II, who ruled from 1740 to 1786, became
the European model of an "Enlightened Despot", inviting and
conversing with French philosophes
like Voltaire, d'Alembert and La Mettrie at his Potsdam palace at the same time
that he continued the work of his predecessors in introducing uniform,
rationalized policies into the state. Kant would speak of Frederick as a
"shining example, with respect to which no monarch surpasses the one whom
we honor" of a head of state who "realizes that there is no danger to
his legislation in allowing his subjects to use reason publicly and to set
before the world their thoughts concerning better formulations of his laws,
even if this involves frank criticism of legislation currently in effect." [3]
Finally, the Aufklärung was not just
a simply a particular set of ideas, but a way of discussing them: Aufklärers gathered together in salons
to read, talk and discuss new ideas together, and created journals to bring
educated opinion scatted throughout the large but unified German lands together
into the "Republic of Letters."
C. Kant's
Pre-Critical Thought
While attending university, Kant was
deeply influenced by the thought of Wolf and of
Without
passing his qualifying exams, Kant left Königsberg - for the longest spell in
his life - to spend nine years working as a private tutor for families living
in the surrounding countryside. These experiences seem to have given him a
sense of the varieties of social life in the East Prussian countryside: he
worked for a Silesian pastor who preached in a Lithuanian community; next, he
taught the sons of a prosperous landowner who owned many serfs; finally, he
became a noted figure in local aristocratic society in the household of Count
Keyserling. [4] Upon
returning to Königsberg in 1755, he published his doctoral dissertation, acquired
the status of privatdozent at the
university, before becoming a full professor in 1770.
Kant's
thought during much of his career - through the 1770s, in any case - was marked
by the Wolfian tradition of what he later called "dogmatic rationalism."
Originating with Descartes, for whom the mind, through its ability to suspend
judgment on any reality until it reached a bedrock of "clear and distinct
ideas", and extending through Leibnitz, for whom the principle of
sufficient reason (the notion that the cause of any thing must be that which is
most susceptible to bring it into being) and the principle of contradiction (which
holds that "A" and "not A" cannot at the same time be true)
provided the basic structure of rationality, rationalism held that the mind's
ability to uncover the logical structure of reality was the primary way in
which certain knowledge could be acquired. Kant used this approach to
investigate the nature of the universe, the existence of God and the meaning of
beauty. But it was only when, later in his life, that he began to read David
Hume that Kant took the philosophical turn that raised his stature from a
significant 18th century philosopher to that of one of the most
challenging thinkers who ever lived.
D. Kant's
Critical/Transcendental Thought.
1.
Awaking
from Dogmatic Slumbers
Rationalism rested on the assumption that
the categories according to which the mind grasped the world actually existed
in the world itself - not just in the mind. This school of epistemology stood
in opposition to the British tradition of empiricism, which maintained that
there were no innate properties of the mind, but that all of its properties
were more or less complex fabrics woven together out of the material provided
by the senses. Though David Hume came out of the latter tradition, his radical
skepticism appeared to challenge both the rationalist and the empiricist school.
According to Hume, it was impossible to assert any rational ideas or categories
as absolute, as they were inevitably merely based on repeated experiences - on
habits, that is, rather than certainties. Kant was particularly impressed by
Hume's analysis of causality. When we say "when the sun rises, it becomes
light", Hume argues, it is impossible to attribute any certainty to this
statement: all that this statement means is that up to now, we have constantly
experienced the conjunction of the sun rising and there being light. But we do
not experience the logical relationship of "cause": rather, this
relationship is merely the nickname that we give to the fact that we constantly
experience them together. In short, one could say that from Hume's perspective,
it is dogmatic to assert that the sun causes light, simply because it flatters
our human consciousness to think of the relationship that we. It is more
accurate to say: we have always seen the sun rising and it getting light
conjoined.
For Kant, one of the main tasks in
philosophy became to purge it of all dogmatism - which he defined as "a
general confidence in principles without a previous criticism of the power of
reason itself." Once dogmatism had been unmasked for what it was - an
unwarranted assumption that the way the mind grasps the world is the way the
world actually is - it was impossible to ever again seek solace in it. Kant
wrote: "whoever has tasted critique is forever disgusted with all the
dogmatic products with which he was formerly obliged to content himself because
his reason needed something and discovered nothing better for entertainment."[5]
Kant's task thus became to take full measure of the
devastating damage which Hume's skepticism inflicted on epistemology, while at
the same time rebuilding a stronger foundation for human knowledge. As he
famously wrote in Prolegomena to Any
Future Metaphysics in 1783: "I freely admit that it was David Hume's reminder
which, many years ago, first aroused me from my dogmatic slumber, and gave my
investigations in the field of speculative philosophy a new direction."[6]
He was then able to turn to the task of his "critical" or
"transcendental" philosophy, undertaken when he was already well into
his 50s - and which is one of the defining moments in modern philosophy.
2.
The
Transcendental Nature of Space and Time
The landmark of Kant's critical turn was
the publication of his Kritik der reinen
Vernunft, or Critique of Pure Reason (often
referred to as the "First Critique") in Königsberg in 1781. The basic
solution which he proposed to overcoming dogmatism was the following: if the
problem with dogmatism was that it presumed the world actually existed as the
mind grasped it, then philosophy had to shift its focus. Rather than
interrogating the world itself, it had to ask what it was possible for the mind
to know in the first place - to find out not what could be learned from
questioning the world, but what questions could be legitimately answered.
Philosophy had to become, as Kant called it, transcendental. He writes: "I entitle transcendental all knowledge which is occupied not so much with objects
as with the mode of our knowledge of objects in so far as this mode of
knowledge is to be possible a priori."*[7]
Kant's first step in his Critique is to investigate the most
immediate form of knowledge: that which we acquire through sensory experience.
To avoid dogmatism, however, we must not assume that what we feel, touch, smell
and so on actually corresponds to the way the world is. After all, Hume taught
him there is no reason to assume the because he always had the sensation of a
bad smell whenever he was near a rotten egg that this actually meant that the
latter causes the former. The
question was rather: what is it that allows us to have sense experiences in the
first place? What is the nature of our receptivity to the things (or at least
what we consider to be) in the outside world?
Kant's answer was that there are necessary
ways in which we (humans, or at least rational beings) perceive the world. To
use Kant's terms, there are certain inevitable "conditions of
possibility" for all sense experiences, that are a priori, that is, not within the experience itself, since they are
rather what organize and constitute the sense experience in the first place.
The philosophical task of determining the a
priori forms of any possible sense experience is what Kant calls
"Transcendental Aesthetic": "transcendental" because it
involves forms that make possible, but are not within experience, and
"aesthetic" because it is the Greek word for sensation.
The two main form of a priori sense experience are space and time. The technical
language should not obscure the radical nature of Kant's claim: space and time
are not - or, to be more precise, it is meaningless to speak of them as -
properties of the world. "Space does not represent any property of things
in themselves", Kant tells us; and as for time, if "we abstract from our mode of inwardly intuiting ourselves
[...] and so take objects as they may be in themselves, then time is
nothing."[8]
Yet Kant's position is not a skeptical
one, as Hume's is. Kant argues that space and time may only be the subjective forms of all sensation, that
is, the way we organize all the "stuff" we perceive in the world. Yet
at the same time, for all that they are subjective, they are necessary. It is impossible, Kant,
believes, to have an experience that is not mediated through the forms of space
and time. He writes: "What objects may be in themselves, and apart from
all this receptivity of our sensibility, remains completely unknown to us. We
know nothing but our mode of perceiving them - a mode which is peculiar to us,
and not necessarily shared in every human being, though, certainly, it is
shared in every human being."[9]
The latter point is the way in which Kant can claim to bring a certain universalism,
or at least a humanism, back into his thought: once we have renounced certainty
about knowledge of the world independently of our way of perceiving it, we can
nonetheless claim real knowledge about how we do see it. In Kant's terms, we
must renounce knowledge about "things in themselves", or noumena, but we can have meaningful
knowledge of things as they appear to us, or phenomena, because we can understand their modes of appearing.
Bertrand Russell described Kant's claim as
follows. Kant teaches us that
"things appear to be thus because the nature of the appearance depends on
the subject in the same way that, if we have blue spectacles, everything
appears to be blue. The categories of Kant are the coloured spectacles of the
mind; truths a priori are the false
appearances produced by those spectacles. Besides, we must know that everybody
has spectacles of the same kind and that the colour of the spectacles never
changes."[10]
Kant himself described his thought as a
Copernican Revolution. According to a recent critic, this term's meaning lies
in the fact that Kant has provided us with the "guiding metaphor of
contemporary thought, of all thought since his time [...] that the world as we
know it is at least partly a creation of the conceptual and linguistic
resources that we bring to it."[11]
E. A
Königsberger philosophy?
Not long after his death, Mme. de Staël introduced
Kant to her French audience by writing: "Kant lived until a very advanced
age, and never did he leave Königsberg; it there that, in the midst of Northern
ice, he spent his entire life meditating the laws of human intelligence."[12]
Commentators have been obsessed with trying to determine the exact relationship
between Kant and the hometown to which he was so attached that he (almost)
never left it. The question might be described as that of the relationship
between the narrow particularism the life he lived and the vast universalism of
his philosophical enterprise (and its universalism is at the very least
plausible: he is still taken very seriously two centuries later). The problem can be broken dealt with in
several possible ways:
1.
Kant's
universalism was made possible by the implicit universalism of Königsberg.
2.
Kant's
universalism existed in spite of the particularism of Königsberg.
3.
Königsberg's
particularism secretly pervades, and undermines, Kant's universalism.
1.
Kant's
universalism was made possible by the implicit universalism of Königsberg.
In many ways, Königsberg was a little
cosmopolis - a city of the world. Though it was becoming increasingly woven
into the administrative network of the Prussian state, its main opening onto
the world remained the trade networks of the Baltic and the intellectual
environment of the university. It was not yet strongly identified with anything
like German nationalism, so it could relish its own
"multiculturalism." Kant himself cultivated the idea that his own
town was cosmopolitan, having once remarked: "A large city, the center of
government, in which the officers of the Government are found; which contains a
university for the culture of the sciences, and is also situated as to have
commerce by sea; which is favored with communication, by means of rivers, with
the interior of the country, as well as with more distant adjoining lands of
various tongues and customs; such a city, for instance, as Königsberg on the
Pregel, may be regarded as a suitable place for enlarging one's knowledge of
men and of the world, a place where this knowledge may be gained even without
travel."[13] One
might wonder how the final remark ties into a critique of empiricism - the
transcendental claim that not experience per se, but reflection on the
conditions of experience, are what philosophy should investigate.
Rosencranz, Kant's 19th century
editor and biographer, found in the social conditions of Königsberg the source
of Kant's universalism. He found there "a remarkable mixture of all
conditions, but not as in many places, a mixture lacking in character or
destructive of individuality. This mixture is supported by the fact that the
town is not small enough to fall under the domination of the ordinary middle
classes, nor big enough to lose itself in the masses, its individualism in a
feeling of nullity. It is precisely big enough to contribute to the philistery
of an ordinary town, and precisely big enough to preserve a connection between
individuality and the whole. In the way one can surmise how children of poor
classes, such as Kant and Hamann, managed to enter into relationship with the
upper classes of society. This enlightened democratic spirit certainly lent
Kant many shades that were later said to be British and French influences. But
Königsberg is still a remarkable town, in that it places before one's eyes all
the phases of the development* of the spirit, from the child in the
forest through the most cultivated of people. Here he can observe, as in all
large towns, the brutality of corruption lying beneath the rags of misery, in
basements as well as in garrets; not only the vulgarity of sailors, but also
the immediate naturalness of the Poles, who, in the summer, on immense
carriages made out of a single piece of iron, bring in, guided by Jewish
speculators, wheat, hemp and bails of hay [check: paillassons] - individuals
who, though baptized, are nevertheless still savages. Finally, as far as Kant
and Hamann are concerned, one must not forget that Königsberg was a Protestant
city, in which one notices little of the Catholic element, even it is not
totally lacking."[14]
Königsberg thus makes possible a form of cosmopolitanism precisely because it
is a moderately sized town, avoiding the distorting conformism brought about by
an overbearing community in a smaller town or the isolating individuality of a
larger one.
Or is its universalism to be explained in
terms of the pretensions of commercial capitalism? Marxist and/or Soviet
critics have frequently drawn the connection between Kant and an emerging
bourgeois consciousness (a commercial, not an industrial bourgeoisie: Germany
was decades away from its industrial revolution), between the way Kant filters
all experience through rational categories and the way in which capitalists
convert all goods into the exchange values expressed in a price.[15]
Yet contemporaries found such a connection lest evident. Amand Saintes
remarked: Königsberg is at the same time a city of scholarship and of commerce,
something that is quite rarely encountered."[16]
Finally, Königsberg's universalism may lie
in the way that it symbolizes human self-assertion against the foreboding
forces of nature. Rosencranz, speaking of the Prussians in his book on Kant,
writes that "a people which surmounts the poverty of nature and which, to
compensate for it, builds for itself an ideal world, can never be ridiculous or
contemptible."[17]
Arseni Goulyga, for his part, writes that "The rigorously built theories
of the philosopher evoke the granite of this town and are animated by its
breath."[18] The
notion of Königsberg as a city overcoming hostile natural elements echoes
Kant's epistemology, which writes off any understanding of the world as it is
in itself in order to assert that it is only the capacities of the human mind
that present themselves to philosophical inquiry (although Kant did develop, in
his Third Critique, a complex theory of "purposiveness in nature").
On the other hand, in Kant's reputation as an "Alleszermalmer", it was understood that the target of his
critiques was not only the a natural world inhospitable to human meaning, but
also the very philosophical constructions by which humans try to make
themselves - falsely - secure in the
world.
2.
Kant's
universalism existed in spite of the particularism of Königsberg.
Perhaps it is just a paradox that a
philosopher like Kant could have been from Königsberg. Whatever the mixture of
people or distinct social dynamics that might have been found there,
Königsberg, from this point of view, simply cannot be considered to have been
very "happening" in the age of Voltaire, Mozart or Frederick II. Simon Blackburn writes of Kant: "He spent
[his life] entirely within a few miles of the desolate coastal town of
Königsberg, or
Yet it is hard to deny that his knowledge
of the world was quite extraordinary, even if he saw little of it. He was the
caricature of an absent-minded professor, with encyclopedic knowledge of the
minutiae of place he never visited, yet unaware of much around him. According
to one biographer: "Once he described Westminster Bridge in the presence
of a resident of London, giving its form, its dimensions, and the arrangements
of the parts, so accurately and minutely, that the Englishman inquired how many
years he had lived in London, and whether he had devoted himself especially to
architecture? With surprise he learned that Kant had never been outside of the
province."[20]
Referring to Kant's Critique of Judgment,
In short, Kant was a world-class
philosopher despite coming from what, at the end of the day, was a second-rate
provincial capital.
3.
Königsberg's
particularism secretly pervades, and undermines, Kant's universalism.
Or is it that Kant is not so much a
paradox, a cosmopolitan preaching in the provinces, as an
all-too-understandable, all-too-human product of his own provincial setting: a
self-important thinker too lacking in imagination and too contemptuous of what
was unfamiliar to him to rise above the stuffy conservatism lying behind by
Königsberg's walls? This is not the most common opinion about Kant, but it can
be found: Anthony Quinton wrote that Kant was "a wild and intellectually
irresponsible arguer. Any innate leaning that way must have been enhanced by
the intellectual isolation of Königsberg, which preserved him from serious
criticism."[22]
III.
The Culture of Aufklärung in 18th
Century Königsberg
The regularity according to which Kant led
his life - his walks, his eating and sleeping habits - paid off: he died in
February 1804, having nearly reached the age of 80, and having completed his
critical project, which he only began publishing in the last quarter of his
life. Still, he questioned, in his later years, the merits of prolonging life
artificially, even if it was through natural means: "It is to this that
the art of prolonging life leads, namely, that one is merely tolerated among
the living, a state which is not the most enjoyable."[23]
Yet Kant was not the only figure of
intellectual significance which 18th Königsberg produced or
attracted, nor was he the sole or most typical representative of the Aufklärer spirit.
A. Other
Königsberger Aufklärers
Theodor
Gottlieb von Hippel (1741
- 1796) was both a successful humorist and novelist, in addition to being an
important political figure in his native Königsberg. His studies at Albertina
were interrupted when he - unlike Kant - seized upon the opportunity to travel
to the court of one of the most famous enlightened despots elsewhere than in Prussia:
the court of Catherine the Great in Saint-Petersburg. Upon returning, he
completed legal studies that eventually led him into a political career in
which he became first the chief bürgermeister, then the President of
Königsberg. During this time, he also acquired for a reputation for his witty,
oddly digressive novels: Lebenslaufe nach
aufsteigender Linie (1778 - 1781), an autobiography interspersed with
random philosophical reflections, and Kreuzund Querzuge des Ritters A bis Z
(1793—I 794), a social satire. He died a rich man in 1796.
Christian
Jacob Kraus (1753 - 1807)
was professor of political economy at the
One of the most important post-Kantian
philosophers was Johann Gottlieb Fichte
(1762 - 1814). Like Kant, he was born into poverty, but was successful enough
in his studies to attend university and, after being thunderstruck by Kant's
writings, made a pilgrimage to Königsberg in 1791. His meeting with Kant on
July 4 left the master unimpressed with the would-be disciple. To impress Kant
with his mastery of critical thought, Fichte promptly wrote An Attempt at a Critique of all Revelation. Drawing
on Kant's moral philosophy, Fichte argued that no Biblical teaching could be
taken as true that portrayed the creator as violating the rational moral law.
Kant was impressed, and the book was published by his editor. For unclear
reasons, the book appeared in print without naming its author, leading many to
assume the work was Kant's own. Once it became known Fichte was the true
author, he acquired notoriety instantly. By 1793, he had received an
appointment that took him from Königsberg to
Finally, the Aufklärer movement did not only emerge out of Christian culture: a
related development was underway in 19th Judaism, known as Haskalah.
After
B. Königsberg
and the Counter-Enlightenment
At the same moment that the Enlightenment
was conquering minds throughout educated
Perhaps the most radical, and at times
bizarre, opponent to the Enlightenment from Königsberg was Johann Georg Hamann (1730 - 1788). An early advocate of mainstream Aufklärer truisms, Hamann, while on a
business trip to
Despite
his personal affection for Kant, Hamann's disposition left him with but little
choice to view his thought as representing anything more than the vain hubris
of a rationalism which denied god's power and detested the world. Kant's
thought partook in the "old, cold prejudice in favor of mathematics"
and testified to a "gnostic
hatred of matter" and a "mystical
love of form". Kant's focus on consciousness ignored the real presence of
matter and bodies in God's order: "The senses
are to the intellect what the stomach is to the vessels which separate
off the finer and higher juices of
the blood: the blood-vessels abstract what they need from the stomach ... our
bodies are nothing but what comes from our parent's stomachs. The stamina and menstrua of our reason
are properly only revelation and tradition."[26]
The
Enlightenment, with its commitment to rational knowledge an universal truths,
cut humans off from meaning experiences with the world as it actually was -
messy, vital, illogical and refractory to classification. His ironic and impudent
writing abounds with metaphors of castration and amputation: "How can a
man who has mutilated his organs feel?", he asks in one place. In 1773, he
mocked an enlightened grammarian who advocated the abolition of the letter
"h" in German because of the arbitrariness of its usage: for Hamann,
the existence of the irrational letter "h" is proof that God is not
the sensible being deduced by logicians, but one whose mysterious ways make the
world rich with subtleties that defy the vain folly of philosophers to
rationalize all aspects of existence.
So,
then, did the thought of the Hamann have some natural affinity with the culture
of Königsberg? Isaiah Berlin suggests it might have: "It may be that
members of backward communities on the edges of a culture that is being radically
transformed, who at once feel powerless to alter the current and are tied more
deeply to the older culture that is being displaced, are peculiarly sensitive
to such change: Naples at the turn of the seventeenth century, and Königsberg
half a century later, were not at the center of events, either politically or
intellectually [...] The type of household in which he [Hamann] was brought up,
the life lived by the Inspector of Baths, as his father was proud to be
described, was being crushed out of existence by the reforms of Frederick and
his genuinely enlightened administrators. [...] Despite the calm and serene
advice that he gave to other troubled spirits to cease from fretting, to
surrender themselves wholly to God, to eat their bread and to drink their wine
in merry contentment, he himself nearly went out of his mind when his salary
was reduced to five thalers and the size of his garden was cut down. He struck
the first blow against the quantified world; his attack was often ill-judged,
but he raised some of the greatest issues of our times by refusing to accept
their advent."[27]
Conclusion
So we are left with a puzzle. Was 18th
century Königsberg a cosmopolitan town that produced a universalist culture?
Was it a provincial town that somehow managed to be a center of Aufklärer universalism? Or was it an
increasingly marginalized city whose position prevented its resident thinkers
from having a plausible view of their world? Which was more authentically
"Königsberger": Kant's view that humans could understand the world
relying solely on their own way of seeing it, or Hamann's faith that messy
reality was everywhere teeming with the presence of the divine? And was there
something about Königsberg that made possible Kant's insight that space and
time were not properties of the world, but rather forms of the human mind?
Michael Behrent, 2002
Copyright © 2002, TABULA RAZA
* "A priori" is Kant's term for that which is prior to - or independent of - experience, as opposed to "a posteriori", which means that which is dependent on experience.
* The French word is "culture", which I assume is a translation of Bildung.
[1] James J. Sheehan, German History, 1770 - 1866 ( Clarendon Press: Oxford, 1989).
[2] Quoted in J. H. W. Stuckenberg, The
Life of Immanuel Kant.
[3] Immanuel Kant, "An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?" Available online at: www.english.upenn.edu/~mgamer/Etexts/kant.html.
[4] See Arsenij Goulyga, Emmanuel Kant, une vie. Trad., Jean-Marie Vaysse. Paris: Aubier,
1985. [
[5] Quoted in Stuckenberg, pp. 112 - 113.
[6] Ibid., pp. p. 233-
234.
[7] Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Norman Kemp Smith translation. (New York: Saint Martin's Press, 1965), p. 59.
[8] Ibid., pp. 71, 77.
[9] Ibid., p. 82.
[10] Bertrand Russell, "The Philosophical
Importance of Mathematical Logic". Available online at
http://pnarae.com/phil/main_phil/russ/math.htm. Significantly, Russell
concludes this passage by adding: "Kant did not deign to tell us how he
knew this."
[11] Simon Blackburn, "Königsberg Confidential", The New Republic,
[12] Germaine de Staël, De l'Allemagne II, Paris:
GF-Flammarion, 1992), p. 127.
[13] From Kant's lectures on "Anthropology", or the science of human nature. Quoted in Stuckenberg.
[14] Rosencranz, Geschichte der Kantschen Philosophie , p. 103, quoted in Amand Saintes, Histoire de la vie et de la philosophie de Kant. (Paris: Cherbuliez; Hambourg: Hérold, 1844), p. 41.
[15] See Goulyga. Versions of this critique of Kant (but not necessarily making the Königsberg connection) have also been made by Georg Lukacs and Theodor Adorno/Max Horkheimer.
[16] Saintes, p. 37.
[17] Quoted in ibid., p. 38.
[18] Goulyga, p. 9.
[19] Blackburn.
[20] Stuckenberg, p. 110.
[21]
[22] Quoted in ibid.
[23] Quoted in Stuckenberg, p. 101
[24] Friedrich Meinecke, The Age of German Liberation, 1795 - 1815. (Peter Paret, ed. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977), p. 36.
[25] Quoted in Isaiah
[26] Ibid., p. 34.
[27] Ibid., pp. 127 - 128.